There is little disputing Robert S. Cohen바카라s statement that 바카라much of our intellectual life, and increasingly large portions of our social and political life, rest on the assumption that we (or, if not we ourselves, then someone whom we trust in these matters) can tell the difference between science and its counterfeit바카라.
But what if we cannot? What if the respect we pay to the science of prediction is respect to a fictive process and little more? What if the untrained human mind is unable to tell the difference beÂtÂÂwÂeen 바카라science and its counterfeit바카라 (just as it is unable to tell the difference between magic and its counterfeit, sleight-of-hand [essentially, between one counterfeit and its counterfeit])?
In predictive mechanisms (as in just about everything else today), the problem is that of boundaries. The demarcation problem in the philosophy of science seeks to address what is science and what is non-science (including anti-science, pseÂudo-science, beliefs, the arts and literature). This article disdains, by virtue of what it focuses on, anti-scientific predictive mechanisms. By virtue of the same, it must therefore depend upon Larry Laudan바카라s prescription that 바카라above all, to have science one must have apodictic certainty.바카라 (바카라The Demise of the Demarcation Problem바카라, in Cohen, R.S.; Laudan, L., Physics, Philosophy and Psychoanalysis: Essays in Honor of Adolf GrĂŒnbaum)
In effect, science must have, as both witness and Âcomponentry, the character of the evidence upon which it stands. As ever, Aristotle beat us to it: αÏοΎΔÎčÎșÏÎčÎșÏ ÏαÏαÎșÏÎźÏÎ±Ï (바카라apodĂctico charaktĂras바카라) translates as 바카라the character of evidence바카라. It refers to clearly demonstrable or clearly undemonstrable propositions. In predictive science, the character of evidence is important, seeing as how evidence of a future predicted will work backwards to establish the verity of the evidence used to predict that future.
And this is where we come to the crux of the problem: The future, being what it isÂ바카라an enigma behind a veil across a sea of suppositions and desires바카라is also clearly undemonstrable. But is the future, though broadly knowable, specifically Âunpredictable? Perhaps, just like the past, the future is hidden by a swirling storm of pixellated data.
There is little point here in placing the tatters of Nostradamus under an electron microscope (the usual one having failed to spot anything convincing). Nor is there any point in pushing the Mayan Weltenende scenario, which, having failed to polish humÂankind off in 2012, has now been reread to mean 2047.
Except that 2047 deserves a mention: It is the year (give or take a year or two) when everything is set to change irrevocably. The planetary climate regime: the finding of Camilo Mora of the UniÂversity of Hawaii that climatic temperature will be 바카라unprecedented바카라. In The SingulÂarity, Ray Kurzweil has runaway AI pegged at 2045Â바카라and it probably won바카라t be all good, although it probably might, who knows. Certainly, oil, accÂording to a BP prediction, will last us until 2047. After that year, everything seems up for grabs. The problem with this is specificityÂ바카라and the fact that previous scientific predictions have all bombed. Take oil:
- In 1914, the US bureau of mines predicted a consolidated future production limit of 5.7 billion barrels of oil바카라a 10-year supply.
- In 1939, the department of the interior predicted that oil reserves in the continental United States would last no more than 13 years.
- In 1951바카라12 years later바카라the depÂartment of the interior바카라s oil and gas division extended its oil-end doomsday prediction by another 13 years.
- In 1972, within three years of its founding, in its significant publication, Limits to Growth, the Club of Rome predicted: 바카라The world will run out of oil by 1991.바카라
- In 2007, BP바카라s Statistical Review of World Energy showed that the world had enough 바카라proven바카라 resÂerves to last another 40 years, at current rates of consumption.
Nobody who is not a right-wing nut or has not financially benefited from the open-handed largesse of oilcos is in any doubt that these catastrophes lie in wait in humankind바카라s futÂure. But, equally, nobody knows when it will all come to pass.
***
TEOTWAWKI (The End Of The World As We Know It) is an absolute favourite of science fiction writers, readers, environmentalists, political scientists and wuthering wonks. It is also a favourite of data-believers such as I: We know the end of the world is nigh; we just don바카라t presume to know when 바카라nigh바카라 is.
In an issue of Wired magazine (April 2000), Bill Joy, co-fÂounder and chief scientist, Sun Microsystems, predicted the end of humankind by 2030, at the outside. The very cutting-Âedge technologies that Kurzweil has exampled as components of the SingularityÂ바카라genetech, robotics, nanotechÂ바카라Joy marked as harbingers of the human extinction event.
There is solid scientific grounding for the essential nonsensicality of prediction models. In their 2006 paper, 바카라CallimacÂhus: Avoiding the Pitfalls of XML for Collaborative Text Analysis바카라 (Literary and Linguistic Computing)바카라the conclusion of 바카라Callimachus: A Virtual Archivist for Electronic Markup Projects바카라Â바카라Jeff Smith, Joel DeShaye and Peter Stoicheff managed to shoot down predictive models as inherently hamstrung by their reliance on past data to generate future data.
The Callimachus project at the University of Saskatchewan was conceived as a way to merge 바카라the robust scalability of formal database technologies with the expressive power and humanist-friendly accessibility of HTML and XML schema바카라. It was first applied to a hypertext of William Faulkner바카라s The Sound and the Fury.
바카라Callimachus was designed to allow the possibility of using a true database application to mark up Faulkner바카라s 1929 novel (The Sound and the Fury) on a token (or word) level.... With this custom database and interface, we can discover when and how a concept appears in the novel. We can discover which characters dwell on what concepts and to what extent. We can discover how many words (how much narrative space) characters use when talking or thinking about specific topics. We can display relationships with charts and graphs computed with any combination of variables.... Faulkner, telling this part of the story through the mind of an idiot, normally provides only obscure clues to mark the mnemonic flashing from one event to Âanother. The narrative does not follow the chronological Âsequence of events in the novel. However, using HTML and JavaScript to tag each event, we built an interface that links events in the narrative sequence with events in a chronologically correct version of the text. For the first time, readers could reorient themselves in the chronology by clicking a button, leaving behind the much more confusing original narrative. The hypÂertext edition helped us clarify our understanding of the novel and yielded some surprising results. We knew that the idiot narrator, named Benjy, would relive an event (such as his grandmother바카라s death), would trigger a ÂseqÂuence of flashbacks, and would often repeatedly return to that initial event. Benjy바카라s memory of his grandmother바카라s death is interrupted 17 times by other flashbacks. When we isolate this event from the interruptions, we notice that it is transmitted chronologically. Hidden in the chaos of so many relÂived events are small, coherent, chronological narratives.바카라 (Vincent Neyt, Review of Stoicheff, Muri, Deshaye, et al (eds): The Sound and the Fury: A Hypertext Edition; Literary and Linguistic Computing, 2004)
It reads all good바카라except that two years after this review was published, Smith, DeShaye and Stoicheff went on to coin the now ubiquitous term, 바카라the fallacy of prescience바카라. It means that the Callimachus project used iffy predictive mechanicals바카라making inferences about ideas and micro-narratives yet to be 바카라discovered바카라 in order to build the very schema, the mechanism, needed to describe them.
In other words, the mechanism of prediction predicts the future. If the basis of the mechanism is ballsed-up, one can expect the reading of the future to be muddled, too. (It gets worse if we bring into the picture Big Data, the much-glorified basis of predictive science today바카라Âbecause few things muddle the statistical waters like Big Data.)
The fallacy of prescience, of course, has illustrious foreparents, all of them applicable, in one form or another, to speculative fiction and non-speculative, 바카라predictive바카라 science. The fallacy of circular reasoning (circulus in probando) ends where 바카라the reasoner begins with what he or she is trying to end up with바카라. The fallacy of the irrelevant conclusion (ignoratio eleÂnchi) is an argument that prima facie seems to address an issue head-on but, in fact, dodges and ducks like crazy. It is a standing favourite in the social media. This fallacy partakes hungrily of the gambler바카라s fallacy, which holds that because something has occurred often within a given period, it will not in future; or because it has not occurred frequently, it is bound to happen. Murphy바카라s law of the raw deal바카라바카라If something rotten can happen, it will바카라바카라is an extension of the gambler바카라s fallacy. As is the 바카라extinction event prediction바카라, which holds that because there have already been five extinction events, another (the Homocene, or Anthropocene, event) is just about here.
In a paper, 바카라Accelerated modern human-induced species losses: Entering the sixth mass extinction바카라 (Science Advances, June 2015), the editors, including Stanford biologist Paul Ehrlich, wrote that 바카라the number of species that have gone extinct in the last century would have taken, depending on the vertebrate taxon, between 800 and 10,000 years to disappear바카라. The paper went on to emphasise: 바카라These estimates reveal an exceptionally rapid loss of biodiversity over the last few centuries, Âindicating that a sixth mass extinction is already under way.바카라
But, as ever, arithmetic does us no good. In the paper quoted above, positing a periodÂ바카라which is nominal, anywayÂ바카라of 바카라betÂween 800 and 10,000 years바카라 is equal to scientific whatiffery. There is no denying that something earth-altering is under way바카라geosocietal anecdotal evidence is on firmer ground here than scientific evidence바카라but there is no saying what shape it will eventually take or when it will happen.
This is where another fallacyÂ바카라a superfallacy, by any yardstick바카라comes into play: Nassim Nicholas Taleb바카라s 바카라Ludic Fallacy바카라바카라explicated in his 2007 book, The Black Swan바카라which is 바카라the misuse of games to model real-life situations바카라. This is something that Taleb figured out on the back of an envelope in a casino. Not unsurprisingly, then, Taleb called his Ludic Fallacy the act of 바카라basing studies of chance on the narrow world of games and dice바카라 (which, being one of a kind with Einstein바카라s huffy, 바카라God does not play dice with the universe바카라, makes one wonder if scientists are not, fundamentally, gamblers).
The adjective ludic originates from the Latin noun ludi (games) and ludus (play, sport, pastime). Ludus also means prank, jest, and diversion, so 바카라the ludic fallacy바카라 might actually be more critical in both intent and content than is usually presumed.
In an earlier book, Fooled By Randomness: The Hidden Role of Chance in Life and the Markets (2001), Taleb had pretty much definitively established that predictive qualities are often perceived바카라but not present바카라in 바카라random patterns바카라, formed by pure chance.
Explaining Taleb, François Daniel Sicart, founder-chairman of Tocqueville Management Corporation, wrote (2007) that 바카라a generalisation such as 바카라all swans are white바카라 merely means that, up to now, only white swans have been observed. But it is enough for one black swan to appear for this conclusion to become entÂirely false. The odds of encountering a white swan are then irrevocably altered. Unfortunately, until a black swan has been observed, no amount of information collected about white swans can help us assess the odds of there being black swans.바카라
And there바카라s the point: Until black swans were 바카라discovered바카라 in Australia in 1697, no one knew they existed, because nobÂody had seen them before. Thereafter, however, Cygnus atratus became part of바카라of all things바카라European culture: black swans became emblematically common. Suddenly, everyone knew someone who knew someone who had seen or kept a flock.
Taleb set a fox among the hens. He ripped apart the book on predictive science. He separated scientific predictability from its prime motivator: human expectation. And he established the 바카라non-computability of the probability of the consequential rare events using scientific methods바카라.
Taleb바카라s prescription worked, even in hindsight. In December 1995, in a well-known piece for InfoWorld, Melancton 바카라Bob바카라 Metcalfe predicted that, in 1996, the internet would collapse under 바카라gigalapses바카라 caused by massive data traffic jams. As co-founder of the Ethernet and founder of 3Com, Metcalfe wasn바카라t fooling around with rubbish doomsaying: the state of the Net had, indeed, raised flags among the Big Data doyens of the digitalverse.
And, yet, no collapse came to pass. If anything, the internet only grew stronger. Among other things, the internet arrived in India on August 15, 1995.
And, at the Sixth Annual World Wide Web Conference in 1997, Metcalfe ate his words바카라literally, by putting his article in a blender and downing it.
***
Almost everything in modern society is about predictive analysis, or how to beat the odds: education (what must I study today to land a good job a decade hence?); jobs (what must I do today to ensure promotivity to a great position five years hence?); health (what vitamins must I pop to be in perfect health when my peers are falling like ninepins all around me?); marketing (I gotta go intercontinental two years from now, so what data do I gather and how must I cruÂnch it?); human expansion (next stop Mars: where바카라s the astrophysical data?); population (if the census is so exact, why is it always wrong?); development policies (why can바카라t I get the right data to formulate working decadal policies?). Et cetera.
All these hairy decisions require some degree of data-Âcrunching. The problems become hairier when the data becÂome too many and the crunching too complex. All development macro-policies are, in essence, predictive: they need, and utilise, mountains of data in order to ensure relevancy sans cesse: and, yet, development policies always impÂlode, because Big Data바카라which policies depend upon for direction, formulation and execution바카라haven바카라t served them well in terms of predicting the future.
For, the issue with Big Data are small data; the issue with small data are micro-data. And the Achilles바카라 heel of micro-Âdata is DatenfĂ€lschung바카라data-falsification, whether deliberate or inadvertent. A smidgen of data-diddling can cause an avalanche of falling dominoes. What the world is facing today is바카라to use the word immortalised by Bret Swanson바카라an 바카라exaflood바카라 of both raw and doctored data. Meanwhile, Big Data has been getting a proper knocking as a vehicle for, well, anything.
Speaking before the US House of Representatives SubÂcommittee on Technology, Information Policy, InterÂgovernÂmÂeÂnÂtal Relations, and Census (March 25, 2003), Jen Que Louie, president of Nautilus Systems Inc, had pointed out four data-mining fallacies:
- Data-mining tools set free will accomplish everything. (No such autopropelled data-mining tools exist.)
- The data-mining process works independent of human oversight. (It doesn바카라t. No software doesÂ바카라yet.)
- Intuition can be built into data-mining software. (Not yet, and perhaps never.)
- Once set loose, data-mining pays its own way. (It doesn바카라t: It needs periodic infusions with upgrades.)
Add to these fallacies two others:
- Data-mining will automatically identify the problems with databases. (It won바카라t. It is not designed to.)
- Data-mining can clean up fuggled databases. (It cannot. Data-mining works with what it has on what it is given.)
In effect, nothing바카라no data, no science, no help from (putative) gods바카라quite helps predict the future. Humankind is stumbling forward more or less blind.
(Kajal Basu is a senior journalist.)